Just how realistic is just war theory? The case for Christian realism
Stanley
Hauerwas ABC Religion and Ethics 2 Sep 2013
http://www.abc.net.au/religion/articles/2013/09/02/3839028.htm
Americans
are a people born of war, and only war can sustain the belief that they are a
people set apart. War is necessary to sustain their belief that they are worthy
of the sacrifices of past wars. Credit: www.shutterstock.com
Pacifists
always bear the burden of proof. They do so because, as attractive as
nonviolence may be, most assume that pacifism just will not work. You may want
to keep a few pacifists around for reminding those burdened with running the
world that what they sometimes have to do is a lesser evil, but pacifism simply
cannot and should not be, even for Christians, a normative stance.
Nonviolence
is assumed to be unworkable, or, to the extent it works at all, it does so only
because it is parasitic on more determinative forms of order secured by
violence. Those committed to nonviolence, in short, are not realistic. In
contrast to pacifism, it is often assumed that just war reflection is
"realistic." It is by no means clear, however, if advocates of just
war have provided an adequate account of what kind of conditions are necessary
for just war to be a realistic alternative for the military policy of a nation.
Just war in the Christian tradition
In
the Christian tradition, realism is often thought to have begun with
Augustine's account of the two cities, hardened into doctrine with Luther's two
kingdoms, and given its most distinctive formulation in the thought of Reinhold
Niebuhr. Thus Augustine is often identified as the Christian theologian who set
the stage for the development of just war reflection that enables Christians to
use violence in a limited way to secure tolerable order. It is assumed,
therefore, that just war is set within the larger framework of a realist view
of the world. With his customary rhetorical brilliance, Luther gave expression
to the realist perspective, asking:
"If anyone
attempted to rule the world by the gospel and to abolish all temporal law and
the sword on the plea that all are baptized and Christian, and that, according
to the gospel, there shall be among them no law or sword - or the need for
either - pray tell me friend, what would he be doing? He would be loosing the
ropes and chains of the savage wild beasts and letting them bite and mangle
everyone, meanwhile insisting that they were harmless, tame, and gentle
creatures; but I would have the proof in my wounds. Just so would the wicked
under the name of Christian abuse evangelical freedom, carry on their
rascality, and insist that they were Christians subject neither to law nor
sword as some are already raving and ranting."
Luther
is under no illusions. War is a plague, but it is a greater plague that war
prevents. Of course, slaying and robbing do not seem the work of love, but,
Luther says, "in truth even this is the work of love." Christians do
not fight for themselves, but for their neighbour. So if they see that there is
a lack of hangmen, constables, judges, lords, or princes, and find they are
qualified they should offer their services and assume these positions. That
"small lack of peace called war," according to Luther, "must set
a limit to this universal, worldwide lack of peace which would destroy
everyone."
Reinhold
Niebuhr understood himself to stand in this "realist" tradition. In
1940 in his "Open Letter (to Richard Roberts)," Niebuhr explains why
he left the Fellowship of Reconciliation. He observes that he does not believe
that "war is merely an 'incident' in history but is a final revelation of
the very character of human history." According to Niebuhr, the
Incarnation is not "redemption" from history as conflict because
sinful egoism continues to express itself at every level of human life, making
it impossible to overcome the contradictions of human history.
Niebuhr,
therefore, accuses pacifists of failing to understand the Reformation doctrine
of "justification by faith." From Niebuhr's perspective, pacifists
are captured by a perfectionism that is more "deeply engulfed in illusion
about human nature than the Catholic pretensions, against which the Reformation
was a protest."
Just war theory as limit to state
action
Paul
Ramsey understood his attempt to recover just war as a theory of
statecraft - that is, that war is justified because our task is first and
foremost to seek justice, to be "an extension within the Christian realism
of Reinhold Niebuhr." Ramsey saw, however, that there was more to be said
about "justice in war than was articulated in Niebuhr's sense of the ambiguities
of politics and his greater/lesser evil doctrine of the use of force."
That "something more" Ramsey took to be the principle of discrimination,
which requires that war be subject to political purpose through which war might
be limited and conducted justly - that is, that non-combatants be protected.
Yet
it is by no means clear if just war reflection can be yoked consistently to
Niebuhrian realism. Augustine's and Luther's "realism" presupposed
there was another city that at least could call into question state powers. For
Niebuhr, realism names the development of states and an international
nation-state system that cannot be challenged. Niebuhrian realism assumes that
war is a permanent reality for the relation between states because no
overriding authority exists that might make war analogous to the police
function of the state. Therefore each political society has the right to wage
war because it is assumed to do so is part of its divinely ordained work of
preservation.
"Realism,"
therefore, names the reality that at the end of the day, in the world of
international relations, the nations with the largest army get to determine
what counts for "justice." To use Augustine or Luther to justify this
understanding of "realism" is in effect to turn a description into a
recommendation.
In
an article entitled "Just War Theory and the Problem of International
Politics," David Baer and Joseph Capizzi admirably try to show
how just war requirements as developed by Ramsey can be reconciled with a
realistic understanding of international relations. They argue that even though
a certain pessimism surrounds a realistic account of international politics, that
does not mean such a view of the world is necessarily amoral. To be sure,
governments have the right to wage war because of their responsibility to a
particular group of neighbours, but that does not mean that governments have a carte
blanche to pursue every kind of interest.
"The same
conception that permits government to wage war also restricts the conditions of
legitimate war making ... Because each government is responsible for only a
limited set of political goods, it must respect the legitimate jurisdiction of
other governments."
But
who is going to enforce the presumption that a government "must respect
the legitimate jurisdiction of other governments"? Baer and Capizzi argue
that Ramsey's understanding of just war as the expression of Christian love by
a third party in defence of the innocent requires that advocates of just war
should favour the establishment of international law and institutions to better
regulate the conduct of states in pursuit of their self-interest. Yet Baer and
Capizzi recognize that international agencies cannot be relied on because there
is no way that such an agency can judge an individual government's
understanding of just cause: "absent effective international institutions,
warring governments are like Augustine's individual pondering self-defence,
moved by the temptation of inordinate self-love."
Baer
and Capizzi argue that a more adequate understanding of just war will combine a
realist understanding of international politics with a commitment to
international order by emphasizing the importance of just intention. This means
that a war can be undertaken only if peace - understood as a concept for a more
"embracing and stable order" - be the reason a state gives for going
to war. The requirement that the intention for going to war be so understood is
an expression of love for the enemy just to the extent that the lasting order
be one that encompasses the interests of the enemy.
My
first reaction to this suggestion is: And people say that pacifists are
unrealistic? The idealism of such realist justifications of just war is
nowhere better seen than in these attempts to fit just war considerations into
the realist presuppositions that shape the behaviour of state actors.
The
likes of Ramsey, Baer and Capizzi are to be commended for trying to recover
just war as a theory of statecraft - that is, as an alternative to the use of
just war as merely a check list to judge if a particular war satisfies enough
of the criteria to be judged just. Yet by doing so, they have made clear the tensions
between the institutions necessary for just war to be a reality and the
presumptions that shape international affairs. For example:
- What would an American foreign policy determined by just war principles look like?
- What would a just war Pentagon look like?
- What kind of virtues would the people of America have to have to sustain a just war foreign policy and Pentagon?
- What kind of training do those in the military have to undergo in order to be willing to take casualties rather than conduct the war unjustly?
- How would those with the patience necessary to insure that a war be a last resort be elected to office?
Those
are the kind of questions that advocates of just war must address before they
accuse pacifists of being "unrealistic."
Ultimately,
I think the lack of realism about realism by American just war advocates has
everything to do with their being American. In particular, American advocates
of just war seem to presume that democratic societies place an inherent limit
on war that more authoritarian societies are unable to do. While such a view is
quite understandable, I would argue that democratic society - at least, the
American version - is unable to set limits on war because it is democratic.
Put
even more strongly, for Americans war is a necessity to sustain our belief that
we are worthy to be recipients of the sacrifices made on our behalf in past wars.
Americans are a people born of and in war, and only war can sustain our belief
that we are a people set apart.
The unreality of war
Realism
is used to dismiss pacifism and to underwrite some version of just war. But it
is not at all clear that the conditions for the possibility of just war are
compatible with realism. At least, it is not clear that just war considerations
can be constitutive of the decision-making processes of governments that must
assume that might makes right. Attempts to justify wars begun and fought on
realist grounds in the name of just war only serve to hide the reality of war.
Yet
war remains a reality. War not only remains a reality, war remains for
Americans our most determinative moral reality. How do you get people who are
taught they are free to follow their own interests to sacrifice themselves and
their children in war? Democracies by their very nature seem to require that
wars be fought in the name of ideals that make war self-justifying. Realists in
the State Department and Pentagon may have no illusions about why American
self-interest requires a war be fought, but Americans cannot fight a war as
cynics. It may be that those who actually have to fight a war will - precisely
because they have faced the reality of war - have no illusions about the
reality of war. But those who would have them fight justify war using
categories that require there be a "next war."
Pacifists
are realists. Indeed, we have no reason to deny that the "realism"
associated with Augustine, Luther and Niebuhr has much to teach us about how
the world works. But that is why we do not trust those who would have us make
sacrifices in the name of preserving a world at war. We believe a sacrifice has
been made that has brought an end to the sacrifice of war.
Augustine
and Luther thought Christians might go to war because they assumed a church
existed that provided an alternative to the sacrificial system war always
threatens to become. When Christians no longer believe that Christ's sacrifice
is sufficient for the salvation of the world, we will find other forms of
sacrificial behaviours that are as compelling as they are idolatrous. In the
process, Christians confuse the sacrifice of war with the sacrifice of Christ.
If
a people does not exist that continually makes Christ present in the world, war
will always threaten to become a sacrificial system. War is a counter church.
War is the most determinative moral experience many people have.
That
is why Christian realism requires the disavowal of war. Christians do not
disavow war because it is often so horrible, but because war, in spite of its
horror - or perhaps because it is so horrible - can be so morally
compelling. That is why the church does not have an alternative to war. The
church is the alternative to war. When Christians lose that reality -
that is, the reality of the church as an alternative to the world's reality -
we abandon the world to the unreality of war.
Comments
Post a Comment