Immutability (Wesley Hill)
http://www.firstthings.com/blogs/firstthoughts/2015/01/the-impassible-god-of-the-bible
First, I want to suggest that whether
impassibility is a “metaphysical a priori”—a conviction brought to
Scripture from somewhere else—is precisely what’s up for debate in recent
theology. To say that the doctrine is not “self-evident in Scripture, nor
necessary in order to hold a fully biblical . . . understanding of God” is to
state one side of the argument, not an agreed-upon conclusion. The recent
biblical and patristic work I gestured toward in my column—the work of folks
like Michael Allen, Paul Gavrilyuk, Matthew Levering, and Kevin Vanhoozer, to
which I’d add names like Donald Gowan, David Bentley Hart, Janet Martin Soskice,
and Scott Swain, among others—is aimed at showing that impassibility is an
entailment of specifically biblical affirmations.
Their argument, in brief, is this. It is, chiefly, the biblical doctrine of
creation—that God is responsible for anything existing at all (Acts 17:24-25;
cf. Isaiah 42:5; Wisdom of Solomon 13-15)—that requires us to speak of God as
categorically different from creatures. Doctrines like simplicity,
immutability, impassibility, and the like are attempts to unpack that
qualitative Creator-creature distinction.
Furthermore, the name of God revealed to Moses at the burning bush (Exodus
3:14) is, in the words of Pope Benedict XVI, “a name and a non-name at one and
the same time.” It is a personal name that allows Moses to grasp God’s
narrative identity in time: “[I am] the God of your ancestors, the God of
Abraham, the God of Isaac, and the God of Jacob” (3:15). But it is also a
non-name insofar as it indicates the utter freedom, self-existence, and otherness
of God: “I am who I am” implies “the One who is,” the God who lives from and
for himself, needing no external maintenance for his ongoing life—indeed,
needing nothing external to be at all. Thus, as D. Stephen
Long has put it, “[T]he so-called metaphysical ‘attributes’ of God
that so many modern theologians have questioned—existence, simplicity,
perfection, limitlessness (infinity), eternity, immutability, and
impassibility—are less indebted to a Greek metaphysics and more explications of
the giving of the divine Name in Holy Scripture.”
The places in Scripture, therefore, that represent God suffering or
undergoing pain or changing God’s course in response to creaturely life are to
be understood in a qualified or analogous sense. God changes and
repents and reacts—but not with any change or repentance or reaction that we
creatures recognize as univocal with our own. Thus, in one of the prime
biblical instances in which God is said to change God’s mind (1 Samuel 15:10,
“I regret that I made Saul king”), we are told just a few verses later that God
does not change God’s mind (15:29, “Moreover the Glory of Israel will not
recant or change his mind; for he is not a mortal, that he should change his
mind”). Divine passion—divine undergoing—is qualified in order to signal
that we err if we project our own changing minds and passions onto God. God
condescends to speak to us in language we can understand, but God’s own life is
qualitatively, not just quantitatively, different than ours.
It is of course perfectly possible to
disagree with this way of thinking. But what I was trying to describe in my
column is that a new form of engagement with the doctrine of divine
impassibility is afoot, regardless of whether one accepts it as a welcome development
or rejects it as a misbegotten errand of retrieval. This new form of engagement
with the doctrine not so much an argument from tradition (“The Church Fathers
said it, so it must be right”) as it is an argument from reexamination
of the tradition (“Here is how the Church Fathers made their case, and
it’s different from what we were told about their arguments in
twentieth-century ‘suffering of God’ theologies”). Put simply, biblical and
patristics scholars are demonstrating that the Church Fathers didn’t simply
borrow impassibility in an uncritical way from their ancient contexts; rather,
they subjected it to exegetical and theological scrutiny, and marshaled
exegetical and theological arguments for their own reworking of it.
Finally, I may say something about what this reassessment of divine
impassibility means for the Incarnation. This is, as one of my friends wrote,
the crux of the issue—pun intended! In much of the recent work I mentioned in
my column, the argument is that it is only by returning to the doctrine of
impassibility that we can make full sense of the claim that it is, in fact, God
who suffered for us in Jesus Christ. Consider the way the
Catholic philosophical theologian Robert Sokolowski has put the matter:
The reason
the pagans could not conceive of anything like the incarnation is that their
gods are part of the world, and the union of any two natures in the world is
bound to be, in some way, unnatural, because of the otherness that lets one
thing be itself only by not being the other. But the Christian God is not a
part of the world and is not a ‘kind’ of being at all. Therefore the
incarnation is not meaningless or impossible or destructive.
Put positively, because the Christian God is radically transcendent
(which “impassibility” gestures toward), therefore God can take human nature to
himself without displacing it or destroying it. And because the transcendent
God has taken human nature to himself, the suffering which God undergoes in
that nature is redemptive, rather than simply passive victimhood and solidarity
with us. Because it is God who suffers in Christ, that suffering is not
simply the suffering a fellow-sufferer who understands but is instead the
suffering of One who is able to end all suffering by overcoming it in
resurrection and ascension and immortality. Paradoxically, perhaps, it is only
by affirming impassibility that we can maintain the deepest soteriological
import of the suffering God takes on himself in and through the Incarnation.
Comments
Post a Comment