The Truth About Our Libertarian Age Why the dogma of democracy doesn't
always make the world better
By Mark Lilla
It is time, twenty-five years on, to
discuss the cold war again. In the decade following the events of 1989,
we spoke about little else. None of us anticipated the
rapid breakup of the Soviet empire, or the equally quick return of Eastern
Europe to constitutional democracy, or the shriveling of the revolutionary
movements that Moscow had long supported. Faced with the unexpected, we engaged
in some uncharacteristic big thinking. Is this the “end of history”? And “what’s
left of the Left?” Then life moved on and our thinking became small
again. Europe’s attention turned toward constructing an amorphous European
Union; America’s attention turned toward political Islamism and the pipe dream
of founding Arab democracies; and the world’s attention turned to Economics
101, our global Core Curriculum. And so, for these reasons and others, we
forgot all about the cold war. Which seemed like a very good thing.
It was not. In truth, we have
not thought nearly enough about the end of the cold war, and especially the
intellectual vacuum that it left behind. If nothing else, the cold war focused
the mind. The ideologies in conflict, whose lineages could be traced back two
centuries, offered clear opposing views of political reality. Now that they are
gone, one would expect things to be much clearer to us, but just the opposite
seems true. Never since the end of World War II, and perhaps since the Russian
Revolution, has political thinking in the West been so shallow and clueless. We
all sense that ominous changes are taking place in our societies, and in other
societies whose destinies will very much shape our own. Yet we lack adequate
concepts or even a vocabulary for describing the world we find ourselves in.
The connection between words and things has snapped. The end of ideology has
not meant the lifting of clouds. It has brought a fog so thick that we can no
longer read what is right before us. We find ourselves in an illegible age.
What is, or was, ideology?
Dictionaries define it as a “system” of ideas and beliefs people hold that
motivate their political action. But the metaphor is inapt. All practical
activity, not just political activity, involves ideas and beliefs. An ideology
does something different: it holds us in its grasp with an enchanting
picture of reality. To follow the optical metaphor, ideology takes an
undifferentiated visual field and brings it into focus, so that objects appear
in a predetermined relation to each other. The political ideologies born out of
the French Revolution were particularly potent because they came with moving
pictures that disclosed how the present emerged from a comprehensible
past and was now moving toward an intelligible future. Two grand narratives
competed for attention in Europe, and then around the world: a progressive one
culminating in a liberating revolution, and an apocalyptic one ending with the
natural order of things restored.
The ideological narrative of the European
left was a cross between Prometheus Bound and the life of
Jesus. Mankind was assumed to be equal to the gods but bound to the rock of
history by religion, hierarchy, property, and false consciousness. For
millennia that was how things stood, until a miracle of incarnation occurred in
1789 and the spirits of freedom and equality became flesh. The problem was that
redemption did not follow. Just as the followers of Jesus had some theological
work to do when his return kept being deferred, so the nineteenth- and
twentieth-century left developed a revolutionary apologetics to make sense of
historical disappointment. It taught that while the French Revolution descended
into Terror and Napoleonic despotism, it did prepare the way for the
pan-European revolutions of 1848. These were short-lived but they inspired the
Paris Commune. That lasted only a few months, but it set the example for the
October Revolution of 1917. True, that was followed by the November Revolution
and then Stalin and his terror. But after World War II the revolution’s
pilgrimage wound its way to China and the Third World, globalizing the struggle
against capitalism and imperialism. Then there was Cambodia, and the music
stopped.
The counter-revolutionary right in
Europe, though much stronger politically in the nineteenth century, could not
offer a narrative nearly as glorious as the left’s. Formed in reaction and
under duress, it was obscure and less inspiring. But in moments of crisis it
could be very compelling. The story it told was a cross between the legend of
the golem and the Book of Revelation. In the best-known version of the golem
story, a rabbi places into the mouth of a clay figure a slip of paper bearing
God’s name on it; the figure then comes alive and rages through a Jewish ghetto
terrorizing its residents until the rabbi snatches the paper back. If we think
of the golem as le peuple, the paper as the writings of Voltaire
and Rousseau, and the destruction of the ghetto as the Terror, we have made our
way into the mind of the reactionary right.
In the legend, the rabbi tames the
golem. The forces of reaction, though, never could control the forces of
revolution in the nineteenth century, which were scientific, economic, and
technological as well. Railroads crisscrossed the unspoiled landscape. Cities
replaced villages and country estates, factories replaced farms, secular
schools replaced religious ones, unshaved politicians replaced dukes and earls,
and the peasants became an undifferentiated mass of brutalized workers. As the
century progressed, a romantic right dreaming of a restored age of sweetness
and light was transformed into an apocalyptic right convinced that it was
living through the Great Tribulation. And when the improbable Russian
Revolution succeeded, and Marxism went from being a small sect to being a
powerful global force, the face of the Antichrist was exposed for the world to
see. The final battle had begun, and into it leapt nationalist redeemers who
ruled their peoples with iron rods and “tread the winepress of the fury of
the wrath of God the Almighty” (Revelation 19:15). We have now made our way
into the mind of fascism.
To speak about such matters is
already, two decades on, to conjure up a lost world. Try to convey the grand
drama of political and intellectual life from 1789 to 1989
to young students today—American, European, even Chinese students—and you are
left feeling like a blind poet singing of lost Atlantis. Fascism for them is
“radical evil,” hence incomprehensible; how it could develop and why it
appealed to millions remains a mystery. Communism, while of course it was for
“many good things,” makes little sense either, especially the faith that people
invested in the Soviet Union. Students simply do not feel the
psychological pull of ideology today, and find it hard to imagine a captive
mind. They find it easier to enter the mental universe of Augustine’s Confessions than
that of Dostoevsky’s and Conrad’s political novels.
That is a mixed blessing. Many
of us over the age of fifty remember arguing with communists and their Marxist
fellow-travelers, and marveling at their impressive—and, in the end, repulsive—adeptness. With
an air of forbearance they would explain that what we took to be significant
facts were actually quite insignificant, and that what seemed trivial was in
fact the crux of the matter. They did not appear to be wearing blinders that
blocked out reality. On the contrary—and this was the problem—they saw
absolutely everything and how it was all connected by occult forces operating
at tremendous distances. When embarrassing
events happened, they instinctively fell into denial. But
very soon the casuistic explications would begin, defending
everything from the Berlin Wall to the Red Brigades, delivered with all the
confidence of a Jesuit in his robes.
Such people are rare today, and good
riddance to them. But it must be admitted that some valuable intellectual
qualities that we developed to confront them have been
disappearing as well. Curiosity, for example, and
ambition. Anti-communist intellectuals used to make the
case that history cannot be mastered by a system or an idea. Societies are
too complex, human motivations too various, and institutions too opaque for us
to get a static picture of reality or discern the invariable laws governing it.
But none of the leading cold war liberals—Raymond Aron, Daniel Bell,
Leszek KoÅ‚akowski, Isaiah Berlin, Ralf Dahrendorf—thought that the
problems Marxism addressed were imaginary or beyond human reckoning. They
resisted Marxist theory because it was, in the end, inadequate to the
task it took up, not because its ambition was wholly misguided. (They were not,
it bears repeating, conservatives.) Bell imagined that the end of ideology
would free up minds to investigate the subtle and unexpected
interactions between the political, economic, and cultural spheres of
modern social life as they develop over time. He did not imagine that the
will to inquire would itself wither. But it has.
This is not how the left of
the left sees it. It thinks that the age of ideology never ended and that a new
“hegemonic worldview” has simply replaced fascism and communism. Americans call
it democratic capitalism and are delighted with it; Europeans call it
neoliberalism and are unhappy with it. There is a good deal to this. It is hard
to deny that the concept of democracy, however misunderstood and traduced, is the
only political form that can claim global, if not universal, recognition today.
And it is true that economic growth is the one common aim of governments around
the world, pursued more often than not with unreflective faith in the cost-free
benefits of free trade, deregulation, and foreign investment.
I would go even further. The social
liberalization that began in a few Western countries in the 1960s is meeting
less resistance among educated urban elites nearly everywhere, and a new
cultural outlook, or at least questioning, has emerged. This outlook treats as
axiomatic the primacy of individual self-determination over traditional social
ties, indifference in matters of religion and sex, and the a priori obligation
to tolerate others. Of course there have also been powerful reactions against
this outlook, even in the West. But outside the Islamic world, where
theological principles still have authority, there are fewer and fewer
objections that persuade people who have no such principles. The recent, and astonishingly
rapid, acceptance of homosexuality and even gay marriage in so many Western
countries—a historically unprecedented transformation of traditional morality
and customs—says more about our time than anything else.
It tells us that this is a libertarian
age. That is not because democracy is on the march (it is regressing in many
places), or because the bounty of the free market has reached everyone (we have
a new class of paupers), or because we are now all free to do as we wish (since
wishes inevitably conflict). No, ours is a libertarian age by default: whatever
ideas or beliefs or feelings muted the demand for individual autonomy in the
past have atrophied. There were no public debates on this and no votes were
taken. Since the cold war ended we have simply found ourselves in a world in
which every advance of the principle of freedom in one sphere advances it in
the others, whether we wish it to or not. The only freedom we are losing is the
freedom to choose our freedoms.
Not everyone is happy about this. The
left, especially in Europe and Latin America, wants to limit economic autonomy
for the public good. Yet they reject out of hand legal limits to individual
autonomy in other spheres, such as surveillance and censorship of the Internet,
which might also serve the public good. They want an uncontrolled cyberspace in
a controlled economy—a technological and sociological impossibility. Those on
the right, whether in China, the United States, or elsewhere, would like the
inverse: a permissive economy with a restrictive culture, which is equally
impossible in the long run. We find ourselves like the man on the speeding
train who tried to stop it by pulling on the seat in front of him.
Yet our libertarianism is not an
ideology in the old sense. It is a dogma. The distinction between ideology and
dogma is worth bearing in mind. Ideology tries to master the historical forces
shaping society by first understanding them. The grand ideologies of the
nineteenth and twentieth centuries did just that, and much too well; since they
were intellectually “totalizing,” they countenanced political totalitarianism.
Our libertarianism operates differently: it is supremely dogmatic, and like
every dogma it sanctions ignorance about the world, and therefore blinds adherents
to its effects in that world. It begins with basic liberal principles—the
sanctity of the individual, the priority of freedom, distrust of public
authority, tolerance—and advances no further. It has no taste for reality, no
curiosity about how we got here or where we are going. There is no libertarian
sociology (an oxymoron) or psychology or philosophy of history. Nor, strictly
speaking, is there a libertarian political theory, since it has no interest in
institutions and has nothing to say about the necessary, and productive,
tension between individual and collective purposes. It is not liberal in a
sense that Montesquieu, the American Framers, Tocqueville, or Mill would have
recognized. They would have seen it as a creed little different from Luther’s sola
fide: give individuals maximum freedom in every aspect of their lives and
all will be well. And if not, then pereat mundus.
Libertarianism’s dogmatic simplicity
explains why people who otherwise share little can subscribe to it:
small-government fundamentalists on the American right, anarchists on the
European and Latin American left, democratization prophets, civil liberties
absolutists, human rights crusaders, neoliberal growth evangelists, rogue
hackers, gun fanatics, porn manufacturers, and Chicago School economists the
world over. The dogma that unites them is implicit and does not require
explication; it is a mentality, a mood, a presumption—what used to be called,
non-pejoratively, a prejudice. Maintaining an ideology requires work because
political developments always threaten its plausibility. Theories must be
tweaked, revisions must be revised. Since ideology makes a claim about the way
the world actually works, it invites and resists refutation. A dogma, by
contrast, does not. That is why our libertarian age is an illegible age.
Consider two examples.
Since the 1980s, the European Union’s
project of economic integration has been governed by neoliberalism, a powerful
form of contemporary libertarianism. There were concrete reasons for this, having
to do with certain failures of the welfare state and the sluggishness
of economies held down by state-run enterprises, over-regulation, and powerful
unions. But as time passed the reasons were forgotten and neoliberalism became
what it is today: a dogma that obscures its real-world effects, which are not
just economic.
It is shocking, for instance, to see
how slow Europeans have been to recognize how seriously the EU neoliberal
approach to economic integration jeopardizes the principles of democratic self-government
that were recovered after World War II. Democracy is about self-determination,
collective and individual; and until now modern constitutional democracies have
developed only within the context of sovereign nation-states. There is a reason
for this. The nation-state represents a compromise of sorts between the
politics of empire and the politics of the village: it is large enough to
encourage people to think beyond their local interests, but not so large that
they feel they have no control over their lives. It provides a clearly
demarcated arena of political contestation and collective action by citizens
who identify with it, and gives them the means of calling governments to
account. Historically speaking, this is a very hard trick to pull off.
From the start there never was any
consensus about just what sort of trick the EU was supposed to be, apart from a
machine to keep the peace and generate prosperity. All agreed that this would
require a diminution of national sovereignty. But at the beginning very little
thinking went into establishing democratic procedures within it, in part
because after the experience with fascism the Founding Fathers did not fully
trust le peuple. Even less thinking went into
how to build public identification with the project—how to turn Scots and
Sicilians into compatriots who feel they share a destiny and recognize the same
institutions. The result is that ordinary Europeans today do not know what
to make of the “European project.”
They see that the weighty
decisions are made in the Brussels bureaucracy or in the European Commission,
whose members are not directly elected. The European Parliament is elected, but
there are no pan-European parties to offer comprehensive programs for governing
and suffer the consequences if they fail to enact them. Voters must choose from
national lists of candidates who can promise nothing and are accountable for
nothing, which encourages irresponsible protest voting. As for
constructing European identity, one need only point out, as many have
done, that the euro note shows not a single historical figure or
place or monument that might resonate with citizens from Glasgow to
Taormina, and that few are aware of the anthem that the EU has chosen for
them. (It is “Ode to Joy,” ironically enough.) Not only has massive
immigration shaken Europeans’ national sense of “we,” so has the continual
expansion of the EU borders to the east and southeast and, who knows, perhaps
one day to the southern rim of the Mediterranean. Since Europe no longer thinks
it has an essence, or a core, or a shared history, or even borders, why should
it reject for membership any nation that says it, too, is Europe?
It is little wonder that citizens
today in both weak and strong nations feel duped and distrust each other. As
Greece and other nations have teetered on the edge of insolvency and
the EU has demanded austerity, their citizens have rightly sensed that
they are losing control over their collective destinies. But
this is also true of the restless German public, which worries that it has
signed an economic suicide pact with profligates. Nationally elected officials
in the weaker states, hoping to stay in office while having to impose
austerity, point to the Germans; the Germans shift blame to the EU solvency
rules. The EU then points to the omniscient financial markets, which refer you
to American bond-rating agencies, which are staffed by MBAs working in cubicles
who have become, faute de mieux, the new sovereigns of Europe. And
what they demand is less democracy and more reliance on technical governments
and economic experts.
Defenders of the European Union
remind us that it has successfully maintained peace for two decades, and warn
that nations must relinquish even more sovereignty if Europe is to cope with
volatile global financial markets and compete with economic behemoths like
China and the United States. This may be so. A pacified Europe is a precious thing,
and a more powerful EU may very well be a necessary thing. But they are not
democratic things.
While Europe has been quietly
chipping away at the foundation of its postwar democracies, the United States
has been trying to build new ones on sand.
Historically, Americans have been
better at living democracy than at understanding it. They consider it a
birthright and a universal aspiration, not a rare form of government that for
two millennia was dismissed as base, unstable, and potentially tyrannical. They
are generally unaware that democracy in the West went from being considered an
irredeemable regime in classical antiquity, to a potentially good one only in
the nineteenth century, to the best form of government only after World War II,
to the sole legitimate regime only in the past twenty-five years.
Ours is a libertarian age by default:
whatever ideas or beliefs or feelings muted the demand for individual autonomy
in the past have atrophied.
The American political science
profession suffers from the same amnesia. During the cold war, scholars
convinced of democracy’s absolute and unique goodness abandoned the traditional
study of non-democratic forms of government, such as monarchy, aristocracy,
oligarchy, and tyranny, and took instead to distinguishing regimes along a
single line running from democracy (good) to totalitarianism (bad). The
academic game then became where along that line to put all the other
“authoritarian” states. (Was Franco’s Spain to the right of Suharto’s
Indonesia, or the other way round?) This way of thinking gave rise to the naïve
assumption that after the collapse of the Soviet Union, countries would
naturally begin making “transitions” from dictatorship and authoritarianism to
democracy, as if by magnetic attraction. That confidence has now evaporated,
and our political scientists have seen that under the cloak of elections many
unpleasant things can grow. But they still want to hold on to their little line
and so they write articles about electoral authoritarianism, competitive
authoritarianism, clan authoritarianism, pseudo-democracies, façade
democracies, and weak democracies. And, just to cover the bases, “hybrid
regimes.”
But in the mind of America’s
political and journalistic classes, only two political categories exist today:
democracy and le déluge. If you assume that democracy is the only
legitimate form of government, that is a perfectly serviceable distinction.
“What should not be, cannot be,” wrote the German poet. Unable or just
unwilling to distinguish the varieties of non-democracy that exist today, we
instead speak of their “human rights records,” which tell us much less than we
think they do. We turn to organizations such as Freedom House, a think tank
that promotes democracy and publicizes human rights abuses around the world. It
produces an influential annual report, Freedom in the World, which
claims to quantify levels of freedom in every country on Earth. It gives them
marks on different factors (rights to political participation, civil liberties,
the press, etc.) and then combines those figures into a composite index number
that indicates whether that country is “free,” “partly free,” or “not free.”
The document reads like a stock report: “this marks the seventh consecutive
year in which countries with declines outnumbered those with improvements.” In
2013, readers were confidently told that, based on the numbers, the “most
noteworthy gains” in freedom in 2012 had been in Egypt, Libya, Burma, and Côte
d’Ivoire. One hardly knows where to begin.
Clearly, the big surprise in
world politics since the cold war’s end is not the advance of liberal democracy
but the reappearance of classic forms of non-democratic political rule in
modern guises. The break-up of the Soviet empire and the “shock therapy” that
followed it produced new oligarchies and kleptocracies that have at their
disposal innovative tools of finance and communication; the advance of
political Islam has placed millions of Muslims, who make up a quarter of the
world’s population, under more restrictive theocratic rule; tribes, clans, and
sectarian groups have become the most important actors in the post-colonial
states of Africa and the Middle East; China has brought back despotic
mercantilism. Each of these political formations has a distinctive nature that
needs to be understood in its own terms, not as a lesser or greater form of
democracy in potentia. The world of nations remains what it has
always been: an aviary.
But ornithology is complicated and
democracy-promotion seems so much simpler. After all, don’t all peoples want to
be well governed and consulted in matters affecting them? Don’t they want to be
secure and treated justly? Don’t they want to escape the humiliations of
poverty? Well, liberal democracy is the best way of achieving these things. That
is the American view—and, true enough, it is shared by many people living in
non-democratic countries. But that does not mean they understand the
implications of democratization and would accept the social and cultural
individualism it would inevitably bring with it. No peoples are as libertarian
as Americans have become today; they prize goods that individualism destroys,
like deference to tradition, a commitment to place, respect for elders,
obligations to family and clan, a devotion to piety and virtue. If they and we
think that they can have it all, then they and we are very much mistaken. These
are the rocks on which the hopes for Arab democracy keep shattering.
The truth is that billions of people
will not be living in liberal democracies in our lifetimes or those of our
children or grandchildren—if ever. This is due not only to culture and mores:
to these must be added ethnic divisions, religious sectarianism, illiteracy,
economic injustice, senseless national borders imposed by colonial powers ...
the list is long. Without the rule of law and a respected constitution, without
professional bureaucracies that treat citizens impartially, without the
subordination of the military to civilian rule, without regulatory bodies to
keep economic transactions transparent, without social norms that encourage
civic engagement and law-abidingness—without all of this, modern liberal
democracy is impossible. So the only sensible question to ask when thinking
about today’s non-democracies is: what’s Plan B?
Nothing reflects the bankruptcy of
today’s political thinking more than our unwillingness to pose this question,
which smacks of racism to the left and defeatism to the right (and both to
liberal hawks). But if the only choices we can imagine are democracy or le
déluge, we exclude the possibility of improving non-democratic regimes
without either trying forcibly to transform them (American-style) or hoping
vainly (European-style) that human rights treaties, humanitarian interventions,
legal sanctions, NGO projects, and bloggers with iPhones will make a lasting
difference. These are the utterly characteristic delusions of our two
continents. The next Nobel Peace Prize should not go to a human rights activist
or an NGO founder. It should go to the thinker or leader
who develops a model of constitutional
theocracy giving Muslim countries a coherent way of recognizing yet
limiting the authority of religious law and making it compatible with good
governance. This would be a historic, though not necessarily democratic, achievement.
No such prize will be given, of
course, and not only because such thinkers and leaders are lacking. To
recognize such an achievement would require abandoning the dogma that
individual freedom is the only or even the highest political good in every
historical circumstance, and accepting that trade-offs are inevitable. It
would mean accepting that, if there is a road from serfdom to democracy, it
will, in long stretches, be paved with non-democracy—as it was in the West. I
am beginning to feel some sympathy for those American officials who led the
occupation of Afghanistan and Iraq ten years ago and immediately began
destroying existing political parties, standing armies, and traditional
institutions of political consultation and authority. The deepest reason for
this colossal blunder was not American hubris or naïveté, though there was
plenty of that. It was that they had no way of thinking about alternatives to
immediate—and in the end, sham—democratization. Where should they have turned?
Whose books should they have read? What model should they have relied on? All
they knew was the prime directive: draft new constitutions, establish
parliaments and presidential offices, then call elections. And after that, it
was the deluge indeed.The libertarian age is an illegible age. It has given birth to a new kind of hubris unlike that of the old master thinkers. Our hubris is to think that we no longer have to think hard or pay attention or look for connections, that all we have to do is stick to our “democratic values” and economic models and faith in the individual and all will be well. Having witnessed unpleasant scenes of intellectual drunkenness, we have become self-satisfied abstainers removed from history and unprepared for the challenges it is already bringing. The end of the cold war destroyed whatever confidence in ideology still remained in the West. But it also seems to have destroyed our will to understand. We have abdicated. The libertarian dogma of our time is turning our polities, economies, and cultures upside down—and blinding us to this by making us even more self-absorbed and incurious than we naturally are. The world we are making with our hands is as remote from our minds as the farthest black hole. Once we had a nostalgia for the future. Today we have an amnesia for the present.
Mark Lilla is Professor of the
Humanities at Columbia University and the author, most recently, of The
Stillborn God: Religion, Politics, and the Modern West (Vintage).
Comments
Post a Comment